If 'B is more likely given A', then 'A is more likely given B' Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Planned maintenance scheduled April 17/18, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern)What is a very intuitive way to teach the Bayes formula to undergraduates?Why does “explaining away” make intuitive sense?What is the intuition behind (M)ANCOVA and when/why should one use it?An example of r.v.s such that their distribution has more (conditional) independencies than their directed graphical modelIntuition for “weights” in simple linear regressionIntuitive explanation of the F-statistic formula?the intuition behind that the variance of increment for Brownian Motion is time intervalWhy is it that when the score variance gets LARGER we get MORE confident about the MLE estimate?Conditional probability question - given pdfIntuition behind infinite CRLBWhy do parametric models learn more slowly by design?

Can Pao de Queijo, and similar foods, be kosher for Passover?

Are variable time comparisons always a security risk in cryptography code?

Why is the black pepper both grey and black?

ListPlot join points by nearest neighbor rather than order

Can a non-EU citizen traveling with me come with me through the EU passport line?

What's the purpose of writing one's academic bio in 3rd person?

Is 1 ppb equal to 1 μg/kg?

How remove lines which are not equal in two buffers?

Can a drone be seen on TCAS?

What is a quick way to find the reverse complement in bash

How can I fade player when goes inside or outside of the area?

What would be the ideal power source for a cybernetic eye?

How is the internal pullup resistor in a microcontroller wired?

Sorting numerically

Why does Python start at index 1 when iterating an array backwards?

Is the Standard Deduction better than Itemized when both are the same amount?

Do you forfeit tax refunds/credits if you aren't required to and don't file by April 15?

What is this single-engine low-wing propeller plane?

Should gear shift center itself while in neutral?

cpython3 different behavior between running a file line by line in interpreter mode and "python3 file"

What is a 'tuning' of a guitar and why would you use it? Doesn't it make it more difficult to play?

What are the options for player characters to create traps?

Single word antonym of "flightless"

How can players work together to take actions that are otherwise impossible?



If 'B is more likely given A', then 'A is more likely given B'



Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara
Planned maintenance scheduled April 17/18, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern)What is a very intuitive way to teach the Bayes formula to undergraduates?Why does “explaining away” make intuitive sense?What is the intuition behind (M)ANCOVA and when/why should one use it?An example of r.v.s such that their distribution has more (conditional) independencies than their directed graphical modelIntuition for “weights” in simple linear regressionIntuitive explanation of the F-statistic formula?the intuition behind that the variance of increment for Brownian Motion is time intervalWhy is it that when the score variance gets LARGER we get MORE confident about the MLE estimate?Conditional probability question - given pdfIntuition behind infinite CRLBWhy do parametric models learn more slowly by design?



.everyoneloves__top-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__mid-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__bot-mid-leaderboard:empty margin-bottom:0;








7












$begingroup$


I am trying to get a clearer intuition behind: "If $A$ makes $B$ more likely then $B$ makes $A$ more likely" i.e




Let $n(S)$ denote the size of the space in which $A$ and $B$ are, then



Claim: $P(B|A)>P(B)$ so $n(AB)/n(A) > n(B)/n(S)$



so $n(AB)/n(B) > n(A)/n(S)$



which is $P(A|B)>P(A)$




I understand the math, but why does this make intuitive sense?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    1 hour ago


















7












$begingroup$


I am trying to get a clearer intuition behind: "If $A$ makes $B$ more likely then $B$ makes $A$ more likely" i.e




Let $n(S)$ denote the size of the space in which $A$ and $B$ are, then



Claim: $P(B|A)>P(B)$ so $n(AB)/n(A) > n(B)/n(S)$



so $n(AB)/n(B) > n(A)/n(S)$



which is $P(A|B)>P(A)$




I understand the math, but why does this make intuitive sense?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    1 hour ago














7












7








7


2



$begingroup$


I am trying to get a clearer intuition behind: "If $A$ makes $B$ more likely then $B$ makes $A$ more likely" i.e




Let $n(S)$ denote the size of the space in which $A$ and $B$ are, then



Claim: $P(B|A)>P(B)$ so $n(AB)/n(A) > n(B)/n(S)$



so $n(AB)/n(B) > n(A)/n(S)$



which is $P(A|B)>P(A)$




I understand the math, but why does this make intuitive sense?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I am trying to get a clearer intuition behind: "If $A$ makes $B$ more likely then $B$ makes $A$ more likely" i.e




Let $n(S)$ denote the size of the space in which $A$ and $B$ are, then



Claim: $P(B|A)>P(B)$ so $n(AB)/n(A) > n(B)/n(S)$



so $n(AB)/n(B) > n(A)/n(S)$



which is $P(A|B)>P(A)$




I understand the math, but why does this make intuitive sense?







probability inference conditional-probability intuition association-measure






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited 1 hour ago









Martijn Weterings

14.8k2064




14.8k2064










asked yesterday









Rahul DeoraRahul Deora

12019




12019











  • $begingroup$
    I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    1 hour ago

















  • $begingroup$
    I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    1 hour ago
















$begingroup$
I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
1 hour ago





$begingroup$
I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
1 hour ago











12 Answers
12






active

oldest

votes


















14












$begingroup$

I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



Bayes' rule:
$$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



$$fracB)P(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



Then $fracB)P(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    9 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
    $endgroup$
    – Acccumulation
    34 mins ago


















9












$begingroup$

Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



And so on.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$








  • 4




    $begingroup$
    That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter Flom
    yesterday






  • 6




    $begingroup$
    @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
    $endgroup$
    – hobbs
    yesterday






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
    $endgroup$
    – hobbs
    yesterday






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter Flom
    21 hours ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter Flom
    21 hours ago


















8












$begingroup$

To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
$$
eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
$$

so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$




















    7












    $begingroup$

    By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



    Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



    What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



    In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



    Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



    So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



    What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



    One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

    Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



    Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.






    share|cite|improve this answer










    New contributor




    Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
    Check out our Code of Conduct.






    $endgroup$












    • $begingroup$
      I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
      $endgroup$
      – Pod
      9 hours ago










    • $begingroup$
      So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
      $endgroup$
      – Rahul Deora
      7 hours ago


















    2












    $begingroup$

    If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



    If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
      $endgroup$
      – mdewey
      yesterday






    • 2




      $begingroup$
      I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
      $endgroup$
      – Dasherman
      yesterday



















    2












    $begingroup$

    If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$




















      2












      $begingroup$

      You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



      $beginarraycc
      beginarraycc
      && A & lnot A & \
      &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
      B& a+b& a & b \
      lnot B & c+d& c & d \
      endarray
      endarray$



      • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
        beginarraycc
        && A & lnot A & \
        &1 & x & 1-x \hline
        B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
        lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
        endarray
        endarray$$
        In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



      • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
        beginarraycc
        && A & lnot A & \
        &1 & x & 1-x \hline
        B& y& a+z & b-z \
        lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
        endarray
        endarray$$



        You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



        Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



      So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



      If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$




















        1












        $begingroup$

        You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



        You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$












        • $begingroup$
          It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
          $endgroup$
          – Martijn Weterings
          23 hours ago



















        1












        $begingroup$

        Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



        $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



        Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



        $$Delta(A|B)
        = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
        = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
        = fracA)mathbbP(B)
        = Delta(B|A).$$



        The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




        $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$




















          1












          $begingroup$

          It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



          • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

          The following is not true:



          • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

          • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

          However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



          • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

          The following is true:



          • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

          • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

          If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



          1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

          2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

          Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



          Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



          Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



          Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



          If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



          However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



          As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).






          share|cite|improve this answer










          New contributor




          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
          Check out our Code of Conduct.






          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
            $endgroup$
            – Rahul Deora
            8 hours ago











          • $begingroup$
            See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
            $endgroup$
            – H4uZ
            7 hours ago


















          0












          $begingroup$

          There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



          Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



          If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$








          • 5




            $begingroup$
            This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
            $endgroup$
            – wizzwizz4
            yesterday



















          0












          $begingroup$

          The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




          If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




          Implication:
          A true -> B true
          A false -> B true or false
          Reverse implication:
          B true -> A true or false
          B false -> A false


          Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




          If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




          Weak implication:
          A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
          A false -> B true or false
          Reverse weak implication:
          B true -> A true or false
          B false -> A false or (unlikely) true





          share|cite|improve this answer








          New contributor




          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
          Check out our Code of Conduct.






          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
            $endgroup$
            – Rahul Deora
            7 hours ago










          • $begingroup$
            @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
            $endgroup$
            – Rainer P.
            5 hours ago









          protected by gung 7 hours ago



          Thank you for your interest in this question.
          Because it has attracted low-quality or spam answers that had to be removed, posting an answer now requires 10 reputation on this site (the association bonus does not count).



          Would you like to answer one of these unanswered questions instead?














          12 Answers
          12






          active

          oldest

          votes








          12 Answers
          12






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes









          14












          $begingroup$

          I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



          Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



          Bayes' rule:
          $$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



          assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



          $$fracB)P(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



          If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



          Then $fracB)P(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



          This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
            $endgroup$
            – probabilityislogic
            9 hours ago










          • $begingroup$
            @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
            $endgroup$
            – Acccumulation
            34 mins ago















          14












          $begingroup$

          I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



          Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



          Bayes' rule:
          $$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



          assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



          $$fracB)P(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



          If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



          Then $fracB)P(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



          This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
            $endgroup$
            – probabilityislogic
            9 hours ago










          • $begingroup$
            @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
            $endgroup$
            – Acccumulation
            34 mins ago













          14












          14








          14





          $begingroup$

          I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



          Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



          Bayes' rule:
          $$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



          assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



          $$fracB)P(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



          If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



          Then $fracB)P(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



          This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$



          I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



          Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



          Bayes' rule:
          $$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



          assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



          $$fracB)P(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



          If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



          Then $fracB)P(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



          This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited yesterday

























          answered yesterday









          Aaron HallAaron Hall

          323215




          323215











          • $begingroup$
            I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
            $endgroup$
            – probabilityislogic
            9 hours ago










          • $begingroup$
            @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
            $endgroup$
            – Acccumulation
            34 mins ago
















          • $begingroup$
            I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
            $endgroup$
            – probabilityislogic
            9 hours ago










          • $begingroup$
            @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
            $endgroup$
            – Acccumulation
            34 mins ago















          $begingroup$
          I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
          $endgroup$
          – probabilityislogic
          9 hours ago




          $begingroup$
          I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
          $endgroup$
          – probabilityislogic
          9 hours ago












          $begingroup$
          @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
          $endgroup$
          – Acccumulation
          34 mins ago




          $begingroup$
          @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
          $endgroup$
          – Acccumulation
          34 mins ago













          9












          $begingroup$

          Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



          But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



          If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

          If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



          If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

          If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



          If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

          If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



          And so on.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$








          • 4




            $begingroup$
            That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            yesterday






          • 6




            $begingroup$
            @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            yesterday






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            yesterday






          • 5




            $begingroup$
            @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            21 hours ago






          • 5




            $begingroup$
            More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            21 hours ago















          9












          $begingroup$

          Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



          But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



          If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

          If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



          If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

          If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



          If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

          If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



          And so on.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$








          • 4




            $begingroup$
            That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            yesterday






          • 6




            $begingroup$
            @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            yesterday






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            yesterday






          • 5




            $begingroup$
            @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            21 hours ago






          • 5




            $begingroup$
            More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            21 hours ago













          9












          9








          9





          $begingroup$

          Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



          But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



          If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

          If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



          If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

          If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



          If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

          If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



          And so on.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$



          Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



          But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



          If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

          If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



          If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

          If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



          If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

          If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



          And so on.







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited yesterday

























          answered yesterday









          Peter FlomPeter Flom

          77.5k12110218




          77.5k12110218







          • 4




            $begingroup$
            That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            yesterday






          • 6




            $begingroup$
            @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            yesterday






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            yesterday






          • 5




            $begingroup$
            @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            21 hours ago






          • 5




            $begingroup$
            More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            21 hours ago












          • 4




            $begingroup$
            That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            yesterday






          • 6




            $begingroup$
            @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            yesterday






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            yesterday






          • 5




            $begingroup$
            @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            21 hours ago






          • 5




            $begingroup$
            More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            21 hours ago







          4




          4




          $begingroup$
          That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
          $endgroup$
          – Peter Flom
          yesterday




          $begingroup$
          That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
          $endgroup$
          – Peter Flom
          yesterday




          6




          6




          $begingroup$
          @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
          $endgroup$
          – hobbs
          yesterday




          $begingroup$
          @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
          $endgroup$
          – hobbs
          yesterday




          2




          2




          $begingroup$
          Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
          $endgroup$
          – hobbs
          yesterday




          $begingroup$
          Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
          $endgroup$
          – hobbs
          yesterday




          5




          5




          $begingroup$
          @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
          $endgroup$
          – Peter Flom
          21 hours ago




          $begingroup$
          @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
          $endgroup$
          – Peter Flom
          21 hours ago




          5




          5




          $begingroup$
          More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
          $endgroup$
          – Peter Flom
          21 hours ago




          $begingroup$
          More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
          $endgroup$
          – Peter Flom
          21 hours ago











          8












          $begingroup$

          To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
          $$
          eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
          $$

          so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



          But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



          The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$

















            8












            $begingroup$

            To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
            $$
            eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
            $$

            so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



            But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



            The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$















              8












              8








              8





              $begingroup$

              To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
              $$
              eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
              $$

              so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



              But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



              The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.






              share|cite|improve this answer











              $endgroup$



              To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
              $$
              eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
              $$

              so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



              But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



              The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.







              share|cite|improve this answer














              share|cite|improve this answer



              share|cite|improve this answer








              edited yesterday

























              answered yesterday









              kjetil b halvorsenkjetil b halvorsen

              32.4k985241




              32.4k985241





















                  7












                  $begingroup$

                  By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



                  Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



                  What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



                  In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



                  Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



                  So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



                  What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



                  One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

                  Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



                  Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.






                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  New contributor




                  Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.






                  $endgroup$












                  • $begingroup$
                    I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Pod
                    9 hours ago










                  • $begingroup$
                    So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
                    $endgroup$
                    – Rahul Deora
                    7 hours ago















                  7












                  $begingroup$

                  By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



                  Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



                  What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



                  In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



                  Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



                  So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



                  What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



                  One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

                  Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



                  Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.






                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  New contributor




                  Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.






                  $endgroup$












                  • $begingroup$
                    I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Pod
                    9 hours ago










                  • $begingroup$
                    So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
                    $endgroup$
                    – Rahul Deora
                    7 hours ago













                  7












                  7








                  7





                  $begingroup$

                  By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



                  Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



                  What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



                  In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



                  Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



                  So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



                  What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



                  One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

                  Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



                  Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.






                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  New contributor




                  Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.






                  $endgroup$



                  By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



                  Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



                  What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



                  In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



                  Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



                  So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



                  What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



                  One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

                  Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



                  Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.







                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  New contributor




                  Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.









                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  edited 7 hours ago





















                  New contributor




                  Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.









                  answered 22 hours ago









                  JosiahJosiah

                  1713




                  1713




                  New contributor




                  Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.





                  New contributor





                  Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.






                  Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.











                  • $begingroup$
                    I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Pod
                    9 hours ago










                  • $begingroup$
                    So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
                    $endgroup$
                    – Rahul Deora
                    7 hours ago
















                  • $begingroup$
                    I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Pod
                    9 hours ago










                  • $begingroup$
                    So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
                    $endgroup$
                    – Rahul Deora
                    7 hours ago















                  $begingroup$
                  I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
                  $endgroup$
                  – Pod
                  9 hours ago




                  $begingroup$
                  I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
                  $endgroup$
                  – Pod
                  9 hours ago












                  $begingroup$
                  So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
                  $endgroup$
                  – Rahul Deora
                  7 hours ago




                  $begingroup$
                  So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
                  $endgroup$
                  – Rahul Deora
                  7 hours ago











                  2












                  $begingroup$

                  If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



                  If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.






                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  $endgroup$








                  • 1




                    $begingroup$
                    This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                    $endgroup$
                    – mdewey
                    yesterday






                  • 2




                    $begingroup$
                    I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Dasherman
                    yesterday
















                  2












                  $begingroup$

                  If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



                  If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.






                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  $endgroup$








                  • 1




                    $begingroup$
                    This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                    $endgroup$
                    – mdewey
                    yesterday






                  • 2




                    $begingroup$
                    I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Dasherman
                    yesterday














                  2












                  2








                  2





                  $begingroup$

                  If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



                  If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.






                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  $endgroup$



                  If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



                  If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.







                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  edited yesterday

























                  answered yesterday









                  DashermanDasherman

                  20116




                  20116







                  • 1




                    $begingroup$
                    This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                    $endgroup$
                    – mdewey
                    yesterday






                  • 2




                    $begingroup$
                    I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Dasherman
                    yesterday













                  • 1




                    $begingroup$
                    This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                    $endgroup$
                    – mdewey
                    yesterday






                  • 2




                    $begingroup$
                    I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Dasherman
                    yesterday








                  1




                  1




                  $begingroup$
                  This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                  $endgroup$
                  – mdewey
                  yesterday




                  $begingroup$
                  This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                  $endgroup$
                  – mdewey
                  yesterday




                  2




                  2




                  $begingroup$
                  I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                  $endgroup$
                  – Dasherman
                  yesterday





                  $begingroup$
                  I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                  $endgroup$
                  – Dasherman
                  yesterday












                  2












                  $begingroup$

                  If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.






                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  $endgroup$

















                    2












                    $begingroup$

                    If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.






                    share|cite|improve this answer











                    $endgroup$















                      2












                      2








                      2





                      $begingroup$

                      If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.






                      share|cite|improve this answer











                      $endgroup$



                      If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.







                      share|cite|improve this answer














                      share|cite|improve this answer



                      share|cite|improve this answer








                      edited yesterday

























                      answered yesterday









                      gunesgunes

                      7,5911316




                      7,5911316





















                          2












                          $begingroup$

                          You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



                          $beginarraycc
                          beginarraycc
                          && A & lnot A & \
                          &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
                          B& a+b& a & b \
                          lnot B & c+d& c & d \
                          endarray
                          endarray$



                          • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
                            beginarraycc
                            && A & lnot A & \
                            &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                            B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
                            lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
                            endarray
                            endarray$$
                            In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



                          • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
                            beginarraycc
                            && A & lnot A & \
                            &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                            B& y& a+z & b-z \
                            lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
                            endarray
                            endarray$$



                            You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



                            Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



                          So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



                          If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.






                          share|cite|improve this answer











                          $endgroup$

















                            2












                            $begingroup$

                            You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



                            $beginarraycc
                            beginarraycc
                            && A & lnot A & \
                            &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
                            B& a+b& a & b \
                            lnot B & c+d& c & d \
                            endarray
                            endarray$



                            • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
                              beginarraycc
                              && A & lnot A & \
                              &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                              B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
                              lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
                              endarray
                              endarray$$
                              In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



                            • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
                              beginarraycc
                              && A & lnot A & \
                              &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                              B& y& a+z & b-z \
                              lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
                              endarray
                              endarray$$



                              You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



                              Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



                            So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



                            If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.






                            share|cite|improve this answer











                            $endgroup$















                              2












                              2








                              2





                              $begingroup$

                              You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



                              $beginarraycc
                              beginarraycc
                              && A & lnot A & \
                              &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
                              B& a+b& a & b \
                              lnot B & c+d& c & d \
                              endarray
                              endarray$



                              • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
                                beginarraycc
                                && A & lnot A & \
                                &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
                                lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
                                endarray
                                endarray$$
                                In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



                              • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
                                beginarraycc
                                && A & lnot A & \
                                &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                B& y& a+z & b-z \
                                lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
                                endarray
                                endarray$$



                                You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



                                Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



                              So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



                              If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.






                              share|cite|improve this answer











                              $endgroup$



                              You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



                              $beginarraycc
                              beginarraycc
                              && A & lnot A & \
                              &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
                              B& a+b& a & b \
                              lnot B & c+d& c & d \
                              endarray
                              endarray$



                              • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
                                beginarraycc
                                && A & lnot A & \
                                &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
                                lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
                                endarray
                                endarray$$
                                In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



                              • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
                                beginarraycc
                                && A & lnot A & \
                                &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                B& y& a+z & b-z \
                                lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
                                endarray
                                endarray$$



                                You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



                                Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



                              So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



                              If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.







                              share|cite|improve this answer














                              share|cite|improve this answer



                              share|cite|improve this answer








                              edited 23 hours ago

























                              answered yesterday









                              Martijn WeteringsMartijn Weterings

                              14.8k2064




                              14.8k2064





















                                  1












                                  $begingroup$

                                  You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



                                  You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?






                                  share|cite|improve this answer









                                  $endgroup$












                                  • $begingroup$
                                    It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                    $endgroup$
                                    – Martijn Weterings
                                    23 hours ago
















                                  1












                                  $begingroup$

                                  You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



                                  You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?






                                  share|cite|improve this answer









                                  $endgroup$












                                  • $begingroup$
                                    It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                    $endgroup$
                                    – Martijn Weterings
                                    23 hours ago














                                  1












                                  1








                                  1





                                  $begingroup$

                                  You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



                                  You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?






                                  share|cite|improve this answer









                                  $endgroup$



                                  You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



                                  You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?







                                  share|cite|improve this answer












                                  share|cite|improve this answer



                                  share|cite|improve this answer










                                  answered yesterday









                                  Hagen von EitzenHagen von Eitzen

                                  1413




                                  1413











                                  • $begingroup$
                                    It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                    $endgroup$
                                    – Martijn Weterings
                                    23 hours ago

















                                  • $begingroup$
                                    It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                    $endgroup$
                                    – Martijn Weterings
                                    23 hours ago
















                                  $begingroup$
                                  It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                  $endgroup$
                                  – Martijn Weterings
                                  23 hours ago





                                  $begingroup$
                                  It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                  $endgroup$
                                  – Martijn Weterings
                                  23 hours ago












                                  1












                                  $begingroup$

                                  Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



                                  $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



                                  Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



                                  $$Delta(A|B)
                                  = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
                                  = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
                                  = fracA)mathbbP(B)
                                  = Delta(B|A).$$



                                  The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




                                  $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.






                                  share|cite|improve this answer









                                  $endgroup$

















                                    1












                                    $begingroup$

                                    Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



                                    $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



                                    Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



                                    $$Delta(A|B)
                                    = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
                                    = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
                                    = fracA)mathbbP(B)
                                    = Delta(B|A).$$



                                    The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




                                    $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.






                                    share|cite|improve this answer









                                    $endgroup$















                                      1












                                      1








                                      1





                                      $begingroup$

                                      Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



                                      $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



                                      Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



                                      $$Delta(A|B)
                                      = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
                                      = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
                                      = fracA)mathbbP(B)
                                      = Delta(B|A).$$



                                      The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




                                      $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.






                                      share|cite|improve this answer









                                      $endgroup$



                                      Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



                                      $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



                                      Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



                                      $$Delta(A|B)
                                      = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
                                      = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
                                      = fracA)mathbbP(B)
                                      = Delta(B|A).$$



                                      The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




                                      $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.







                                      share|cite|improve this answer












                                      share|cite|improve this answer



                                      share|cite|improve this answer










                                      answered 17 hours ago









                                      BenBen

                                      28.3k233129




                                      28.3k233129





















                                          1












                                          $begingroup$

                                          It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



                                          • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

                                          The following is not true:



                                          • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

                                          • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

                                          However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



                                          • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

                                          The following is true:



                                          • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

                                          • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

                                          If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



                                          1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                          2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                          Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



                                          Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



                                          Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



                                          Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



                                          If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



                                          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                          However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



                                          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                          As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).






                                          share|cite|improve this answer










                                          New contributor




                                          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                          $endgroup$












                                          • $begingroup$
                                            This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            8 hours ago











                                          • $begingroup$
                                            See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – H4uZ
                                            7 hours ago















                                          1












                                          $begingroup$

                                          It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



                                          • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

                                          The following is not true:



                                          • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

                                          • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

                                          However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



                                          • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

                                          The following is true:



                                          • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

                                          • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

                                          If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



                                          1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                          2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                          Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



                                          Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



                                          Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



                                          Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



                                          If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



                                          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                          However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



                                          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                          As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).






                                          share|cite|improve this answer










                                          New contributor




                                          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                          $endgroup$












                                          • $begingroup$
                                            This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            8 hours ago











                                          • $begingroup$
                                            See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – H4uZ
                                            7 hours ago













                                          1












                                          1








                                          1





                                          $begingroup$

                                          It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



                                          • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

                                          The following is not true:



                                          • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

                                          • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

                                          However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



                                          • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

                                          The following is true:



                                          • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

                                          • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

                                          If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



                                          1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                          2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                          Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



                                          Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



                                          Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



                                          Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



                                          If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



                                          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                          However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



                                          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                          As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).






                                          share|cite|improve this answer










                                          New contributor




                                          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                          $endgroup$



                                          It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



                                          • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

                                          The following is not true:



                                          • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

                                          • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

                                          However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



                                          • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

                                          The following is true:



                                          • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

                                          • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

                                          If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



                                          1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                          2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                          Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



                                          Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



                                          Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



                                          Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



                                          If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



                                          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                          However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



                                          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                          As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).







                                          share|cite|improve this answer










                                          New contributor




                                          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.









                                          share|cite|improve this answer



                                          share|cite|improve this answer








                                          edited 7 hours ago





















                                          New contributor




                                          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.









                                          answered 9 hours ago









                                          H4uZH4uZ

                                          112




                                          112




                                          New contributor




                                          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.





                                          New contributor





                                          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.











                                          • $begingroup$
                                            This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            8 hours ago











                                          • $begingroup$
                                            See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – H4uZ
                                            7 hours ago
















                                          • $begingroup$
                                            This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            8 hours ago











                                          • $begingroup$
                                            See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – H4uZ
                                            7 hours ago















                                          $begingroup$
                                          This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – Rahul Deora
                                          8 hours ago





                                          $begingroup$
                                          This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – Rahul Deora
                                          8 hours ago













                                          $begingroup$
                                          See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – H4uZ
                                          7 hours ago




                                          $begingroup$
                                          See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – H4uZ
                                          7 hours ago











                                          0












                                          $begingroup$

                                          There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



                                          Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



                                          If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.






                                          share|cite|improve this answer









                                          $endgroup$








                                          • 5




                                            $begingroup$
                                            This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – wizzwizz4
                                            yesterday
















                                          0












                                          $begingroup$

                                          There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



                                          Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



                                          If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.






                                          share|cite|improve this answer









                                          $endgroup$








                                          • 5




                                            $begingroup$
                                            This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – wizzwizz4
                                            yesterday














                                          0












                                          0








                                          0





                                          $begingroup$

                                          There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



                                          Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



                                          If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.






                                          share|cite|improve this answer









                                          $endgroup$



                                          There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



                                          Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



                                          If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.







                                          share|cite|improve this answer












                                          share|cite|improve this answer



                                          share|cite|improve this answer










                                          answered yesterday









                                          gnasher729gnasher729

                                          48133




                                          48133







                                          • 5




                                            $begingroup$
                                            This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – wizzwizz4
                                            yesterday













                                          • 5




                                            $begingroup$
                                            This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – wizzwizz4
                                            yesterday








                                          5




                                          5




                                          $begingroup$
                                          This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – wizzwizz4
                                          yesterday





                                          $begingroup$
                                          This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – wizzwizz4
                                          yesterday












                                          0












                                          $begingroup$

                                          The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




                                          If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




                                          Implication:
                                          A true -> B true
                                          A false -> B true or false
                                          Reverse implication:
                                          B true -> A true or false
                                          B false -> A false


                                          Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




                                          If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




                                          Weak implication:
                                          A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
                                          A false -> B true or false
                                          Reverse weak implication:
                                          B true -> A true or false
                                          B false -> A false or (unlikely) true





                                          share|cite|improve this answer








                                          New contributor




                                          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                          $endgroup$












                                          • $begingroup$
                                            I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            7 hours ago










                                          • $begingroup$
                                            @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rainer P.
                                            5 hours ago















                                          0












                                          $begingroup$

                                          The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




                                          If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




                                          Implication:
                                          A true -> B true
                                          A false -> B true or false
                                          Reverse implication:
                                          B true -> A true or false
                                          B false -> A false


                                          Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




                                          If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




                                          Weak implication:
                                          A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
                                          A false -> B true or false
                                          Reverse weak implication:
                                          B true -> A true or false
                                          B false -> A false or (unlikely) true





                                          share|cite|improve this answer








                                          New contributor




                                          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                          $endgroup$












                                          • $begingroup$
                                            I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            7 hours ago










                                          • $begingroup$
                                            @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rainer P.
                                            5 hours ago













                                          0












                                          0








                                          0





                                          $begingroup$

                                          The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




                                          If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




                                          Implication:
                                          A true -> B true
                                          A false -> B true or false
                                          Reverse implication:
                                          B true -> A true or false
                                          B false -> A false


                                          Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




                                          If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




                                          Weak implication:
                                          A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
                                          A false -> B true or false
                                          Reverse weak implication:
                                          B true -> A true or false
                                          B false -> A false or (unlikely) true





                                          share|cite|improve this answer








                                          New contributor




                                          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                          $endgroup$



                                          The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




                                          If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




                                          Implication:
                                          A true -> B true
                                          A false -> B true or false
                                          Reverse implication:
                                          B true -> A true or false
                                          B false -> A false


                                          Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




                                          If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




                                          Weak implication:
                                          A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
                                          A false -> B true or false
                                          Reverse weak implication:
                                          B true -> A true or false
                                          B false -> A false or (unlikely) true






                                          share|cite|improve this answer








                                          New contributor




                                          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.









                                          share|cite|improve this answer



                                          share|cite|improve this answer






                                          New contributor




                                          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.









                                          answered 8 hours ago









                                          Rainer P.Rainer P.

                                          101




                                          101




                                          New contributor




                                          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.





                                          New contributor





                                          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                          Check out our Code of Conduct.











                                          • $begingroup$
                                            I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            7 hours ago










                                          • $begingroup$
                                            @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rainer P.
                                            5 hours ago
















                                          • $begingroup$
                                            I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            7 hours ago










                                          • $begingroup$
                                            @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rainer P.
                                            5 hours ago















                                          $begingroup$
                                          I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – Rahul Deora
                                          7 hours ago




                                          $begingroup$
                                          I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – Rahul Deora
                                          7 hours ago












                                          $begingroup$
                                          @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – Rainer P.
                                          5 hours ago




                                          $begingroup$
                                          @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                          $endgroup$
                                          – Rainer P.
                                          5 hours ago





                                          protected by gung 7 hours ago



                                          Thank you for your interest in this question.
                                          Because it has attracted low-quality or spam answers that had to be removed, posting an answer now requires 10 reputation on this site (the association bonus does not count).



                                          Would you like to answer one of these unanswered questions instead?



                                          Popular posts from this blog

                                          Oświęcim Innehåll Historia | Källor | Externa länkar | Navigeringsmeny50°2′18″N 19°13′17″Ö / 50.03833°N 19.22139°Ö / 50.03833; 19.2213950°2′18″N 19°13′17″Ö / 50.03833°N 19.22139°Ö / 50.03833; 19.221393089658Nordisk familjebok, AuschwitzInsidan tro och existensJewish Community i OświęcimAuschwitz Jewish Center: MuseumAuschwitz Jewish Center

                                          Valle di Casies Indice Geografia fisica | Origini del nome | Storia | Società | Amministrazione | Sport | Note | Bibliografia | Voci correlate | Altri progetti | Collegamenti esterni | Menu di navigazione46°46′N 12°11′E / 46.766667°N 12.183333°E46.766667; 12.183333 (Valle di Casies)46°46′N 12°11′E / 46.766667°N 12.183333°E46.766667; 12.183333 (Valle di Casies)Sito istituzionaleAstat Censimento della popolazione 2011 - Determinazione della consistenza dei tre gruppi linguistici della Provincia Autonoma di Bolzano-Alto Adige - giugno 2012Numeri e fattiValle di CasiesDato IstatTabella dei gradi/giorno dei Comuni italiani raggruppati per Regione e Provincia26 agosto 1993, n. 412Heraldry of the World: GsiesStatistiche I.StatValCasies.comWikimedia CommonsWikimedia CommonsValle di CasiesSito ufficialeValle di CasiesMM14870458910042978-6

                                          Typsetting diagram chases (with TikZ?) Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Planned maintenance scheduled April 17/18, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern)How to define the default vertical distance between nodes?Draw edge on arcNumerical conditional within tikz keys?TikZ: Drawing an arc from an intersection to an intersectionDrawing rectilinear curves in Tikz, aka an Etch-a-Sketch drawingLine up nested tikz enviroments or how to get rid of themHow to place nodes in an absolute coordinate system in tikzCommutative diagram with curve connecting between nodesTikz with standalone: pinning tikz coordinates to page cmDrawing a Decision Diagram with Tikz and layout manager